Argument
My argument
from the incoherence of actually existing infinitesimals has the following
structure:
1.
Infinitesimal quantities can’t exist;
2.
If actual infinities can exist, actual infinitesimals must exist;
3.
Therefore, actual infinities can’t exist.
Although
Cantor, who invented the mathematics of transfinite numbers, rejected
infinitesimals, mathematicians have continued to develop analyses based on them,
as mathematically legitimate as are transfinite numbers, but few philosophers try
to justify actual infinitesimals, which
have some of the characteristics of zero and some characteristics of positive numbers. When you add an infinitesimal to a real number, it’s like adding zero.
But when you multiply an infinitesimal by infinity, you sometimes get a finite
quantity: the points on a line are of infinitesimal dimension, in that they
occupy no space (as if they were zero duration), yet compose lines finite in
extent.
Few
advocate actual infinitesimals because an actually existing infinitesimal is
indistinguishable from zero. For however small a quantity you choose, it’s
obvious that you can make it yet smaller. The role of zero as a boundary
accounts for why it’s obvious you can always reduce a quantity. If I deny you
can, you reply that since you can reduce it to zero and the function is
continuous, you necessarily can reduce any given quantity—precluding actual infinitesimals. When I raise the same argument about an infinite set, you can’t
reply that you can always make the set bigger; if I say add an element, you
reply that the sets are still the same size (cardinality). The boundary imposed by zero is counterpoint for
infinitesimals to the openness of infinity, but actual-infinitesimals’
incoherence suggests that infinity is
similarly infirm.
Can more be
said to establish that the conclusion about actual infinitesimal quantities
also applies to actual infinite quantities? Consider again the points on a
3-inch line segment. If there are infinitely many, then each must be
infinitesimal. Since there are no actual infinitesimals, there are no actual
infinities of points.
But this
conclusion depends on the actual infinity being embedded in a finite
quantity—although, as will be seen, rejecting bounded infinities alone travels
metaphysical mileage. For boundless infinities, consider the number of quarks
in a supposed universe of infinitely many. Form the ratio between the number of
quarks in our galaxy and the infinite number of quarks in the universe. The ratio
isn’t zero because infinitely many galaxies would still form a null proportion
to the universal total; it’s not any real number because many of them would
then add up to more than the total universe. This ratio must be infinitesimal. Since
infinitesimals don’t exist, neither do unbounded infinities (hence, infinite
quantities in general, their being either bounded or unbounded).
Infinitesimals and
Zeno’s paradox
Rejecting
actually existing infinities is what really resolves Zeno’s paradox, and it
resolves it by way of finding that infinitesimals don’t exist. Zeno’s paradox,
perhaps the most intriguing logical puzzle in philosophy, purports to show that
motion is impossible. In the version I’ll use, the paradox analyzes my walk
from the middle of the room to the wall as decomposable into an infinite series
of walks, each reducing the remaining distance by one-half. The paradox posits
that completing an infinite series is self-contradictory: infinite means uncompletable.
I can never reach the wall, but the same logic applies to any distance; hence,
motion is proven impossible.
The
standard view holds that the invention of the integral calculus completely
resolved the paradox by refuting the premise that an infinite series can’t be
completed. Mathematically, the infinite series of times actually does sum to a
finite value, which equals the time required to walk the distance; Zeno’s deficiency
is pronounced to be that the mathematics of infinite series was yet to be
invented. But the answer only shows that (apparent) motion is mathematically
tractable; it doesn’t show how it can occur. Mathematical tractability is at
the expense of logical rigor because it is achieved by ignoring the distinction
between exclusive and inclusive limits. When I stroll to the wall, the wall
represents an inclusive limit—I actually reach the wall. When I integrate the
series created by adding half the remaining distance, I only approach the limit
equated with the wall. Calculus can be developed in terms of infinitesimals,
and in those terms, the series comes infinitesimally close to the limit, and in
this context, we treat the infinitesimal as if it were zero. As we’ve seen,
actual infinity and infinitesimals are inseparable, certainly where, as here,
the actual infinity is bounded. The calculus solves the paradox only if actual infinitesimals
exist—but they don’t.
Zeno’s misdirection
can now be reconceived as—while correctly denying the existence of actual
infinity—falsely affirming the existence of its counterpart, the infinitesimal. The paradox assumes that while I’m uninterruptedly walking to
the wall, I occupy a series of infinitesimally small points in space and time,
such that I am at a point at a specific time the same as if I had
stopped.
Although
the objection to analyzing motion in Zeno’s manner was apparently raised as
early as Aristotle, the calculus seems to have obscured the metaphysical
project more than illuminating it. Logician Graham Priest (Beyond the Limits of Thought (2003)) argues that Zeno’s paradox
shows that actual infinities can exist, by the following thought experiment.
Priest asks that you imagine that rather than walking continuously to the wall,
I stop for two seconds at each halfway point. Priest claims the series would
then complete, but his argument shows that he doesn’t understand that the
paradox depends on the points occupied being infinitesimal. Despite the early
recognition that (what we now call) infinitesimals are at the root of the
paradox, philosophers today don’t always grasp the correct metaphysical analysis.
Distinguishing actual
and potential infinities
Recognizing
that infinitesimals are mathematical fictions solidifies the distinction
between actual and potential infinity. The reason that mathematical infinities
are not just consistent but are useful is that potential infinities can
exist. Zeno’s paradox conceives motion as an actual infinity of sub-trips, but, in reality, all that can be
shown is that the sub-trips are potentially
infinite. There’s no limit to how many times you can subdivide the path, but traversing
it doesn’t automatically subdivide it infinitely, which result would require
that there be infinitesimal quantities. This understanding reinforces the point
about dubious physical theories that posit an
infinity of worlds.
It’s been argued that some versions of the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics that invoke an uncountable infinity of worlds don't require actual
infinity any more than does the existence of a line segment, which can be
decomposed into uncountably many segments, but an infinite plurality of worlds does
not avoid actual infinity. We exist
in one of those worlds. Many worlds, unlike infinitesimals and the conceptual
line segments employing them, must be conceived as actually existing.
[Edit September 15, 2013.] Corrected claim that many-worlds theories of quantum mechanics posit an infinity of worlds. Some many-worlds theories do, and some don't. This argument applies only to those versions positing infinite worlds.
[Edit September 15, 2013.] Corrected claim that many-worlds theories of quantum mechanics posit an infinity of worlds. Some many-worlds theories do, and some don't. This argument applies only to those versions positing infinite worlds.