Is status a positional good?
As the
concept of social status itself
attains higher status (through employment in evolutionary psychology), class
struggles over the material conditions of life are recognized as impregnated
with status aspirations. The conclusion may be drawn or implied that these
conflicts are inherently wasteful: we’d be better off if people accepted their
lot, because status is a positional good—a zero-sum game—what is won by some is
lost by others. (See, for example, Robin Hanson’s Inequality
talk is about grabbing.) But it also seems that a society beset with
severe status inequality will suffer status deflation.
One approach
to the question of whether status is a positional good is whether status is
(implicitly) measured using an ordinal scale of measurement or a higher scale,
interval or ratio, where ordinal scales express only rank, whereas interval and
ratio scales express degrees of difference. An example of an ordinal scale
expressing social status is military rank. The status of the rank of major
depends on the mass of soldiers a major outranks and the number who outrank the
major, so, if half of the captains are promoted to major, the major’s status
declines.
Social
status can seem similar to military rank, but (I contend) this is a confusion:
the social status of an entire population can rise or fall (inflate or deflate),
because the main component of social status is prestige, which has ratio properties. The confusion results from conflating prestige with
dominance, more primitive and prototypical, but prestige is a ratio scale, not
an ordinal scale like dominance, because it results from summing over weighted dominance
relations. Consider our major in contrast to a lieutenant under his command. The
lieutenant may have received higher grades in the military academy, he may come
from a wealthier family, and he may be the president of a nonmilitary club in
which the major participates as an ordinary member. Which has more prestige? The point
is that the question makes sense; we combine information about position in
various separate dominance
hierarchies with other information about their potential power to determine their
prestige, the information’s additivity implying that prestige is at least an interval
scale (probably a ratio scale), not a mere ordinal scale like dominance. Concern
with prestige (as distinct from dominance) is a human-specific trait, with few
roots other than dominance in our primate psychology.
Why prestige?
Evolutionary
psychologists propose that prestige
(usually referred to simply as status,
a convention I will abide) reflects a person’s value as an ally: a high-status
person is a powerful ally. (The person with the highest prestige is God,
the most powerful ally.) Other primates appear to have only dominance, which
suffices for simian calculations because apes, living in a single hierarchy,
don’t need to sum over different hierarchies. Humans live embedded in multiple
social hierarchies—at root, dominance relations—which must be weighted and
added to appraise an individual’s value in alliances.
If
primordial alliances were exclusively alliances pitted against other allied humans,
prestige could still be a zero-sum game despite its ratio scaling. But the
alliances formed primordially weren’t exclusively competitive alliances:
alliances were presumably formed for foraging and child care. Ratio-scaled prestige, a currency spanning dominance
hierarchies, allows more and broader alliances.
Two
distinct explanatory tasks regarding prestige concern its evolutionary function
and its individual motivation. Evolutionary psychologists hypothesize that
status derives from the differential value of persons as allies. The
quest for prestige aligns the individual’s efforts with adaptation: by pursuing
prestige, one becomes a more powerful ally, deriving the corresponding social
(and reproductive) advantages. But the mechanism is more complex and itself
provides additional clues about function. Prestige is a reaction formation
against envy. This agrees with the observation that we accord prestige to
those we would otherwise envy. (See Theodor Reik, Love and Lust: On the Psychoanalysis of Romantic and Sexual Emotion
regarding the idealization process—rooted in unconscious envy—in romantic love.
“Reaction formation” is a psychodynamic mechanism involving experiencing the
opposite of certain thoughts, to deny them conscious access.)
Since status
is commonly
perceived value as ally, status deflation means decreased willingness to
rely on—to ally with—others. In 11.3,
I discussed opinionation as a pathology of belief-opinion confusion: we are
opinionated when we fail to rely sufficiently on the opinions of experts.
Status deflation causes irrational opinionation (as well as other adverse
societal effects, including
some relating to macroeconomics). The modern
expression of the tendency toward excessively narrow alliances is lack of
regard for the opinions of most others, including experts. At the same time, (one's own) status deflation
increases the experienced envy. In societies where status is
most deflated (typically, traditional agrarian societies), this two-pronged attack
on the sublimation of envy results in the bullheadedness of the peasant.
Countering status deflation and generating
inflation.
Economic
inequality is a manifestation of status deflation as well as one of its causes
(as I maintained in 21.0.)
In modern capitalist societies, the
main ways of reducing inequality have been restricted immigration (to
reduce the supply of labor and increase its price) and progressive taxation.
But these policies have been applied sporadically and are only practiced weakly
in most advanced countries. Within Europe, the Common Market has opened
borders, and in the United States, wealth inequality is so high it rivals some
third-world countries. The reason stringent immigration
control and progressive taxation are only sporadically applied is that these
methods don’t correspond to any humanly valued relational model—which as
Alan P. Fiske (Structures
of Social Life (1991)) shows, enable
the moralization
of social practices and, as John Bolender elaborates (The
Self-Organizing Social Mind (2010)),
correspond to the four scales of measurement. (Communal/Sharing is nominal,
Authority/Ranking is ordinal, Equality/Matching is interval, and Market/Pricing
is ratio.) A flat tax employs a ratio scale, a fact that helps account for its
ideological popularity despite its practical infirmity. To human intuition,
progressive tax rates are arbitrary. As to immigration control, absolute
restriction would correspond to Communal/Sharing, but like the flat tax rate, mere
reduction of immigration rates doesn’t
form an intuitively compelling public
policy. (This is not to disparage the instrumental use of either
immigration control or progressive taxation.)
State socialism,
on the other hand, can be grounded in intuitive metrics: equality matching
(interval scale) embedded in communal sharing (nominal scale). It has proven not only to
provide a greater degree of status equality (thus
status inflation) but also to be more durable.
No comments:
Post a Comment